![]() |
Disputations''For true and false will in no better way be revealed and uncovered than in resistance to a contradiction.'' -- St. Thomas Aquinas Navigation
Disputed sites
Undisputed sites
< # MetroBlogs ? >
Atom Feed
May 2002 June 2002 July 2002 August 2002 September 2002 October 2002 November 2002 December 2002 January 2003 February 2003 March 2003 April 2003 May 2003 June 2003 July 2003 August 2003 September 2003 October 2003 November 2003 December 2003 January 2004 February 2004 March 2004 April 2004 May 2004 June 2004 July 2004 August 2004 September 2004 October 2004 November 2004 December 2004 January 2005 February 2005 March 2005 April 2005 May 2005 June 2005 July 2005 August 2005 September 2005 October 2005 November 2005 December 2005 January 2006 February 2006 March 2006 April 2006 May 2006 June 2006 July 2006 August 2006 September 2006 October 2006 November 2006 December 2006 January 2007 February 2007 March 2007 April 2007 May 2007 June 2007 July 2007 August 2007 September 2007 October 2007 November 2007 December 2007 February 2008 March 2008 April 2008 May 2008 June 2008 July 2008 August 2008 September 2008 October 2008 November 2008 December 2008 January 2009 February 2009 March 2009 April 2009 May 2009 June 2009 July 2009 August 2009 September 2009 October 2009 November 2009 December 2009 January 2010 February 2010 March 2010 April 2010 May 2010 July 2010 August 2010 September 2010 October 2010 November 2010 December 2010 January 2011 February 2011 March 2011 April 2011 May 2011 June 2011 July 2011 August 2011 September 2011 October 2011 November 2011 April 2012 May 2012 June 2012 July 2012 August 2012 September 2012 October 2012 November 2012 December 2012 January 2013 February 2013 March 2013 April 2013 May 2013 June 2013 July 2013 August 2013 September 2013 October 2013 November 2013 December 2013 January 2014 February 2014 March 2014 April 2014 May 2014 June 2014 July 2014 August 2014 September 2014 October 2014 November 2014 December 2014 January 2015 February 2015 March 2015 April 2015 May 2015 June 2015 July 2015 August 2015 September 2015 October 2015 November 2015 December 2015 January 2016 February 2016 April 2016 July 2016 August 2016 October 2016 December 2016 January 2017 September 2017 February 2020 June 2020 July 2020 September 2020 May 2024 |
Sunday, February 28, 2010
A resolution
So how do I think Evangelium Vitae, which makes limiting the use of the death penalty to cases "when it would not be possible otherwise to defend society," and the Catechism, which uses the language of self-defense (e.g., "defending human lives against the unjust aggressor"), are to be understood as developing the doctrine of St. Thomas? First, what do I know? Second, I'm not convinced it's a development that goes beyond what the blessed John Paul II wrote in his encyclical (quoting, as it happens, a paragraph in the Catechism that was rewritten to accommodate what he wrote in EV); namely, that "bloodless means... to defend human lives against an aggressor and to protect public order and the safety of persons... better correspond to the concrete conditions of the common good and are more in conformity to the dignity of the human person." Moreover, in the same paragraph of EV (n. 56), the Pope does use the term "punishment" in reference to the death penalty three times. So it can hardly be claimed that the fact the Catechism doesn't call the death penalty a punishment means Church teaching has developed to the point that it is not regarded as a punishment. Third, if you do want to think of the death penalty in terms of self-defense, it's a trivial matter: ![]() See? There's no need to put it under the double effect rubric; St. Thomas long ago provided for the "referred to the common good" justification for killing done in the name of the one responsible for the common good. It's all there. Granted, CCC 2263 might seem to argue that yes, warfare and execution are both double-effect cases: The legitimate defense of persons and societies is not an exception to the prohibition against the murder of the innocent that constitutes intentional killing. "The act of self-defense can have a double effect: the preservation of one's own life; and the killing of the aggressor.... The one is intended, the other is not."65But the internal quotation is from ST II-II, 64, 7, and refers explicitly and only to an individual acting on his own behalf. That the Catechism should not be read as teaching that the legitimate defense of societies is always a matter of double effect is evident by the fact that doing so is absurd. Link | 89 comments | Tweet Saturday, February 27, 2010
The simple art of murder
On the off chance that someone both cares about and doesn't understand what's going on with the "What is the object of the act of execution?" question: Here's a diagram of the types of killing St. Thomas discusses under the vice of murder, which he opposes to the virtue of justice: Now, nobody's arguing about killing plants, or about whether clerics may kill. So here's a subset of the above figure, with the justifications St. Thomas gives for those types of killing he considers lawful: While of course St. Thomas is not himself the Magisterium, the Church has essentially adopted his teaching as her own. There are those who maintain that the development of teaching that occurred under the pontificate of the blessed John Paul II -- in particular on the lawfulness of the death penalty, which St. Thomas considered a matter of a public authority killing a sinner for the sake of the common good -- constitutes a substantial change, such that executions and killing in warfare become subtypes of self-defense: Not quite to-may-to, to-mah-to, since the claim is that the justification of both the death penalty and killing in warfare is the same as the justification of an individual killing an attacker in self-defense -- viz, double-effect reasoning, according to which only the saving of one's life is the intended effect and the slaying of the aggressor is the unintended effect, with only such force as is proportionate to self-defense being used. This leads to the curious notion that a soldier may shoot an enemy soldier only if he does not intend to kill him, and the notion so ludicrous only an intellectual would believe it that an executioner may execute a criminal only if he does not intend to kill him. UPDATED with a new caption for Figure 3, to make explicit my disapproval. Link | 18 comments | Tweet Friday, February 26, 2010
Yeesh
Jean Bethke Elshtain is kind of a big deal in political philosophy. She is not, however, a moral theologian, nor is she Catholic, so she makes an odd source for Marc Thiessen to quote (introducing her as "one of America's great moral theologians") in explaining the Catholic moral concept of casuistry. Still, the author gets to choose his own sources, and if his editor okays it he's good to go. Now, though, I read this in a New York Times's article about the Thiessen affair: Jean Bethke Elshtain, of the University of Chicago, said that while soldiers or politicians might have to commit necessary evils sometimes, they "still stand convicted before God, if you are thinking theologically."Assuming the reporter didn't mangle it (and from that last sentence, mangling what comes before is a distinct possibility), Professor Elshtain thinks something can be both necessary and evil. So we have a political speechwriter who doesn't know what "wrong" means turning to a political philosopher who doesn't know what "evil" means for moral instruction. And what do you know? Waterboarding wins! (NYT link via Coalition for Clarity.) Labels: On torture Link | 4 comments | Tweet
Amateur theologizing
Phillip and I are engaged in a discussion in the comments on this post on the nature of licit capital punishment. He opened with this comment: I suspect the moral object in the death penalty is not the taking of life. Rather the moral object seems to be defense against an unjust attack.My reply: Yeah, except if he's still alive, they throw the switch again.We kicked this thesis around some, and I've formulated my position thusly: It is absolutely, utterly ludicrous to say that an executioner does not intend to execute his victim.To expound on the possibilities: If you say the executioner does not intend to execute his victim and know it's sophistry, then you're a sophist. If you say it and don't know it's sophistry, then you're an idiot. I gather that there are good intentions in saying such ludicrous things as "in using lethal force against a dangerous criminal, the state is justified only in using force proportionate to render him incapable of causing harm; if he dies as an consequence, his death would have to remain praeter intentionem (i.e., unintended)." After all, Evangelium Vitae does change the Church's teaching on capital punishment, and it's the job of theologians to understand the implications. However, as I commented to Phillip, the blessed John Paul II was no sophist, so to read him as saying the executioner does not intend the death of the executed is to misread him. I would also suggest that theologians ought to pick their heads up from time to time and actually listen to what they're saying. Link | 13 comments | Tweet Wednesday, February 24, 2010
Epistles are written by the winners
We were talking about St. Paul's Letter to the Galatians at our Lay Fraternities of Saint Dominic chapter meeting last night. (For my Catholic readers, that's the one he wrote when he was stomping mad that people were saying you had to follow the Jewish Law to be Christian.) The thought occurred that the Judaizers (as they're called) who come under St. Paul's fire and brimstone ("if anyone preaches to you a gospel other than the one that you received, let that one be accursed!") probably didn't know they were Judaizers. I expect they considered themselves orthodox Christians, fighting the good fight against old Paganizer Paul. Jewish Christianity is what they had seen, been taught, and lived for a decade or more before all this nonsense about Gentile Christianity started being spread about. How were they to know that they were the villains of the piece? Jesus Himself told people to listen to the Pharisees, and that He had not come to abolish the Law. Who was Paul of Tarsus to say otherwise? I take two things from this line of thought: First, a reminder that it's a good idea to try to distinguish error from motive, and leave judging the motive to God. Second, an awareness that anyone can mistake the incidental for the essential, if they do not keep their eyes fixed on Jesus Christ, Who gave Himself for our sins. Link | 6 comments | Tweet
Reintegration
It's looking like my new and improved bodily integrity -- now fortified with natural functions! -- doesn't really fly, in that (to take up Tommy's suggested phrase) we can lose the use of a natural function through means that are not really directed against bodily integrity as the term has traditionally been understood. I'd still say, though, that we can talk about natural functions -- meaning the functions of movement, nutrition, reproduction, thought, and so forth that accord with human nature -- as a consequence of bodily integrity, in that a body with full integrity is capable of all natural functions (or possesses them at least in potency, or some such way of putting it). Saying it the right way round, bodily integrity is the state of the body being whole and capable of functioning according to its nature. (I had "unwounded" in there, too, but if bruises, stripes, and the like are understood as contrary to wholeness, then I think it's implied by the other two conditions; also, this way bodily integrity is defined entirely in terms of possessing goods rather than lacking evils.) In which case, acts touching on bodily integrity must touch on the wholeness and capability of natural functions of the body, but -- contrary to my previous suggestion -- acts that touch only on the circumstantial ability of the body to exercise natural functions which it possesses the potential to exercise do not touch on bodily integrity directly, but only by analogy. Link | 1 comments | Tweet Tuesday, February 23, 2010
A question of integrity
An objection Tommy raised to my argument in this post causes me to think a little harder about what constitutes respect for the bodily integrity of the human person. In Casti Connubii, his 1930 encyclical on Christian marriage, Pope Piux XI writes: 70. Public magistrates have no direct power over the bodies of their subjects; therefore, where no crime has taken place and there is no cause present for grave punishment, they can never directly harm, or tamper with the integrity of the body, either for the reasons of eugenics or for any other reason. St. Thomas teaches this when inquiring whether human judges for the sake of preventing future evils can inflict punishment, he admits that the power indeed exists as regards certain other forms of evil, but justly and properly denies it as regards the maiming of the body. "No one who is guiltless may be punished by a human tribunal either by flogging to death, or mutilation, or by beating." [ST II-II,108,4,ad 2]Integrity of the human body entails a kind of physical "wholeness," a wholeness of both physical completeness and natural functions -- or, if you prefer, of a physical completeness that itself entails the ability to function naturally. I think everyone agrees that the sort of physical wholeness confirmable by physical inspection is a part of bodily integrity, so that any sort of intentional wounding of the body -- severing, stabbing, flogging, crushing, and so forth -- is an act directed against bodily integrity. I'm not sure how far down the "natural functions" path everyone is willing to travel. I'd suggest, though, that if the Church counts having children as a natural function the impedance of which is contrary to bodily integrity, then such things as standing and stretching would also count. If crippling someone so that he can no longer stand is contrary to his bodily integrity, then would not binding him so that he can't stand also be? Note that I haven't mentioned morality yet. (The Pope did, in the words I quoted, but he's allowed to.) To this point I'm just trying to scope the term "bodily integrity," and in particular to include within its scope the notion of the ability of the body to function naturally -- which is to say, to function according to the nature of the human body. Another example of what I'm trying to suggest: It is a natural function of the human body to see. Insofar as an act renders a body unfit to see, the act is contrary to bodily integrity. So now I'm wondering, how far does the act of blindfolding render a body unfit to see? Link | 7 comments | Tweet Monday, February 22, 2010
Quis, quid, ubi, quibus auxiliis, cur, quomodo, quando
Things really heat up in ST I-II, 7, 3. Who isn't dying to know whether the circumstances are properly set forth in Ethic. iii? In the article, "Whether the circumstances are properly set forth in the third book of Ethics?," St. Thomas characterizes the different ways something can be the accident of an act and enumerates these ways as (more or less) those circumstances identified by both Aristotle and by Cicero (in On Invention):
"Time" and "place" are pretty straightforward. The "mode of acting" is, you might say, the adverb of the act. It modifies the act in a way worth mentioning, but not in a way that changes what the act itself is. The examples St. Thomas provides are of a man walking quickly or slowly and of a man striking hard or softly. The "what" of the act is the act's immediate effect. If I am baking a pie, the what of my act is (God willing) a baked pie. It may seem a bit odd to say that "what is done" is only a circumstance, an accident, of the act, and not the act itself. In fact, we do often conflate the act with its effect. We might, for example, speak of the act of saving someone from drowning, when strictly speaking "saving someone from drowning" is really the effect of the act of jumping into the lake and drawing the person out. "Why" is just what it sounds like. The "about what" (which, St. Thomas says, Cicero includes in the "what") is simply the material or stuff that what is done is done to; the ingredients of my pie, for example. "Who" is who, and "by what aids" are the circumstantial tools or instruments used by the "who" upon the "about what" to effect the "what". All good to know. But what really glitters like a diamond in this article is the reply to objection 3, which objection says that "the causes of an act seem to belong to its substance," so why, about what, who, and by what aids shouldn't count as circumstances. Labels: Treatise on Human Acts Link | 3 comments | Tweet
Send them over here
A report that the issue of reducing the number of dioceses in Ireland was mentioned by Cardinals Giovanni Battista Re and Tarcisio Bertone(prefect of the Congregation for Bishops and Vatican Secretary of State, respectively) during meetings last week with the Irish bishops reminds one that the U.S. could sure use a few new dioceses. It wouldn't be the first time the Irish Church has provided assistance to us. I think in particular of the monster archdioceses like Los Angeles (rumors of its division are already bouncing around) and Chicago (six auxiliary bishops = one fat clue), though I can't help but think, parochially (ha), that my own Archdiocese of Washington could use another suffragan diocese. Not that there's anything wrong with the Diocese of St. Thomas in the Virgin Islands, but -- and I say this with great respect for my brothers and sisters in Christ who, under Bishop Harper, make the Gospel of Jesus Christ present where they live -- visions of rum swizzles do little to add to the gravitas of Washingon's portfolio. (First link via Luke Coppen's Morning Catholic must-reads.) Link | 0 comments | Tweet Sunday, February 21, 2010
Torture's not so bad!
It would seem that American-style waterboarding of prisoners for information is not torture. Torture causes persistent physical and/or psychological damage to the victim. But American-style waterboarding of prisoners for information does not cause persistent physical and/or psychological damage to the victim. Therefore, American-style waterboarding of prisoners for information is not torture. I reply, torture is physical or moral violence directed against the bodily integrity of the victim, as the Catechism of the Catholic Church says (n. 2297). But offenses against bodily integrity need not cause persistent effects, as is shown by the fact that kidnapping and hostage-taking are also offenses against the bodily integrity of the victim, and they need cause persistent effects no more than waterboarding. So the absence of persistent effects is not proof that an act is not torture. A speculation: People often think of torture as necessarily causing persistent injury because most methods of torture actually do, or at least can, cause persistent injury. The combination of a will to torture and a will to avoid persistent injury is relatively rare in history. An observation: I didn't mention this in my reply because it's not necessary to refute the argument in the first paragraph, but: The truth of that argument's other premise -- "American-style waterboarding of prisoners for information does not cause persistent physical and/or psychological damage to the victim" -- is by no means established. In particular, it is not established by anecdotal accounts of American-style waterboarding of SERE trainees, for two reasons. First, among the many circumstantial differences between waterboarding prisoners and waterboarding trainees is the difference in relationship between the waterboarder and the waterboardee, and among the differences that follow from the difference in relationship is that being waterboarded is a different psychological experience for a prisoner than it is for a trainee. The second reason anecdotal accounts of SERE trainees does not establish that prisoners do not suffer persistent injury is that some anecdotal accounts of SERE trainees include persistent psychological injury. UPDATED with an observation. Labels: On torture Link | 35 comments | Tweet Thursday, February 18, 2010
Soup stock
Another good link from T.S. O'Rama, this one to a piece by Mrs. Darwin on inspirational blogging: I've grown very wary of the pretty conclusion, the spiritual lesson learned, the great insight gained through the grind of daily life. I know why writers use this trick, and I've done it myself -- hard up for something, anything, to post, I remember this little anecdote that could just do for posting if I can put some little inspirational twist on it. And people seem to eat the stuff up, so it must be fine, right?Reminding me of Chesterton's answer to criticisms of those who write for effect; to paraphrase, "What the devil shall we write for? Effectlessness?" The counter-counter-criticism would be, "Effected writing isn't effective." Mrs. Darwin continues: I don't even want inspiration from the internet anymore. I've been trying to immerse myself in Scripture, reading passages from the Wisdom literature each night. This is real. This is what can reach into my soul and open me to God in a way that reading a blog can never emulate. Who can say anything that Qoheleth didn't cover 23 centuries ago?I look at my own chicken soup posts as bread upon the waters: If there's a duck out there who eats it (and some uninspired posts of mine have been reported to really hit the spot), good! But I shouldn't insist on it happening, or even bet on it, and I certainly shouldn't think of writing it as a solemn duty. Link | 2 comments | Tweet
Java and jive
T.S. O'Rama offers a Mother Angelica anecdote on coffee and Lent: The caller was wrestling over whether or not, or even if she could, surrender coffee as a Lenten penance.Coincidentally, I've been wondering whether, and how seriously, to propose breaking your self-imposed Lenten fasts every Thursday (to pick a convenient day). That way, the fasts won't become ends in themselves. 16 DAYS WITHOUT ADDING SALT TO HIS FOOD AT THE TABLE Link | 6 comments | Tweet Wednesday, February 17, 2010
Of the circumstances of human acts, pt. 1
St. Thomas discusses the circumstances of human acts in the four articles of ST I-II, 7. In article 1, he defines circumstances as "conditions [that] are outside the substance of an act, and yet in some way touch the human act." (This means that the circumstances of an act are its accidents -- an accident being something that belongs to something but doesn't belong to the thing's substance -- but the term "accident" probably doesn't add much nowadays to that definition.) In particular, circumstances touch the human act by being in the actor together with the act. So, as we'll find out, when an act occurs is always a circumstance of an act, even if when it occurs plays no part in either the actor's will or in the overall morality. (A thief who steals whatever he can whenever he can, for example, takes no account of the circumstances of when he steals, nor does when he steals something affect the morality of his theft.) But I'm getting ahead of myself, since it's not until article 2 that St. Thomas proposes that circumstances are a matter of interest to the theologian. He gives three reasons:
Labels: Treatise on Human Acts Link | 0 comments | Tweet Tuesday, February 16, 2010
What does "pro-life" mean?
Politically speaking, "pro-life" is the term groups founded to oppose legal abortion settled on to describe themselves. They've got first dibs on the expression. If you want to complain that in practice "pro-life" just means "anti-abortion," go wait in line for the time machine.* While they're waiting, though, what do we say to the people who insist that opposing plastic water bottles is also a pro-life issue? My proposal is to use the Catechism to provide a framework for "life issues" that is as good as any and better than most. Here is the Catechism's framework for discussing the Fifth Commandment, "You shall not kill" (click to enlarge): ![]() I propose, then, that for an organization, social program, political platform, etc., to be legitimately called "pro-life," it is necessary and sufficient that
* The line for the time machine starts anywhere. Just leave a note saying where you're waiting. Link | 223 comments | Tweet Monday, February 15, 2010
To those Catholic
I have a question and an observation. The question: What does it say about your party that this is an issue that could be used as an excuse to vote for the other party? The observation: Your party can make it go away as a political issue by explicitly and meaningfully rejecting any endorsement of it. Labels: On torture Link | 26 comments | Tweet
Comment policy update
My Haloscan-era comment policy was one of reserving the right to delete and edit comments and to ban commenters in a purely capricious manner. This remains intact, though I don't actually seem to be able to edit comments or ban commenters with Blogger. This part is new: I reserve the right to refer to any anonymous commenter as "Mr. Bimbim," and to treat their comments as though they were the playful antics of a fluffy wuffy cutie patootie doggy woggy. My intent is to irritate anonymous commenters into using the "Name/URL" option -- and, obviously, to entertain myself. Link | 5 comments | Tweet
The eyes of Luke
What struck me in hearing yesterday's Gospel proclaimed were these words: And raising his eyes toward his disciples he said....In preaching both the Beatitudes and the, er, Woeitudes, Jesus has his eyes on His disciples. For what it's worth, here are all the verses in Luke that, in the NAB translation, mention eyes (I leave out one mention of the eye of a needle): Eyes that see:
Link | 6 comments | Tweet Sunday, February 14, 2010
A general objection
It would seem that American-style waterboarding of prisoners is not torture. American-style waterboarding of prisoners is specified by the object of pouring water into the nose and mouth of a person. This is the same object as American-style waterboarding of SERE trainees, and American-style waterboarding of SERE trainees is not considered wrong in itself, much less torture. Since they share the same object, and differ only in circumstances and intention, they must share the same objective moral quality. And since American-style waterboarding of SERE trainees is regarded as objectively moral, so must American-style waterboarding of prisoners be regarded as objectively moral. But torture is objectively immoral, as the United States Catholic Catechism for Adults says. Therefore, American-style waterboarding of prisoners cannot be regarded as torture. I reply, a description of the object of an act is not necessarily identical to the object itself. The description may be too general, encompassing multiple acts with different specific ends, as for example "undue foretelling of the future" describes both divination by dreams and divination by demons, which are two distinct acts that are further specified by the circumstances through which the foretelling occurs. The description may also be too narrow, failing to specify any proper end or set of ends of the will; this happens, for example, if the description is excessively physical, as with "to push someone," which is only a part of multiple distinct objects such as "to help someone by pushing them" and "to injure someone by pushing them." Thus, the fact that the objects of both American-style waterboarding of SERE trainees and American-style waterboarding of prisoners can be described as "to pour water into the nose and mouth of a person" does not demonstrate that they are the same species of moral act, nor prove that American-style waterboarding of prisoners is not torture. In particular, it seems to be an example of a too-narrow description that fails to specify one or more proper ends of the will, as waterboarding for training would seem to be an act related to fortitude and waterboarding for interrogation of prisoners an act related to justice. UPDATED for brevity and (one hopes) general improvement. Labels: On torture Link | 10 comments | Tweet Friday, February 12, 2010
Fear, concupiscence, and ignorance
Sounds like the motto of my college newspaper, but actually they're the topics of the last three articles of ST I-II, 6, on the voluntary and the involuntary in relation to human acts. In article 6, St. Thomas (following Aristotle and St. Gregory of Nyssa) teaches that things done through fear are essentially voluntary. Fear regards a future evil as something to be avoided, but we can only act in the here and now, when that future evil does not yet exist. Sailors who throw their cargo overboard in a storm do so voluntarily; given their knowledge, they genuinely wish to lighten the ship. Still, throwing their cargo overboard is contrary to their will apart from the circumstances of the storm, so he allows that acting through fear is involuntary in that respect. In article 7, he says that, not only does concupiscence not cause involuntariness, but it makes things voluntary. Concupiscence causes us to desire evil things, thinking them good. The desire is real, even if the goodness of what is desired is not. Article 8 introduces a threefold relationship between ignorance and the act of the will. An actor may be ignorant of something regarding his act voluntarily -- either because he wishes not to know or because he has chosen not to learn what he can and should know. If an actor weren't ignorant, he might still do what he's doing in ignorance. St. Thomas proposes the following relationships between ignorance and willing:
On the other hand, voluntary ignorance of things an actor can and should know broadens the scope of his ignorance, and so increases the chance he will unwittingly do something he would do even if he weren't ignorant. So a man who kills his enemy, thinking he is killing a deer, when he should have known he was killing his enemy, is guilty of imprudence but not murder. UPDATED with a description of affected ignorance and ignorance of evil choice. Labels: Treatise on Human Acts Link | 8 comments | Tweet Thursday, February 11, 2010
Violence and the will
In articles 4 and 5 of ST I-II, 6, St. Thomas addresses how violence can affect the will and the voluntariness of acts. Violence in this context means an outside force acting against an interior inclination. A violent shove, for example, might act against your interior inclination to walk down the street. In article 4, St. Thomas says that violence cannot be done directly to the will. He describes the act of the will as twofold: the "immediate act" of the will that we might call "to wish"; and an act of the will commanded by the act of wishing, which in turn commands a person's other powers to fulfill that wish (by, for example, walking somewhere or saying something). While violence can certainly prevent a person from walking somewhere or saying something, it can't prevent a person who wishes to do so from wishing to do so. (Violence can cause a person to wish something he wouldn't have wished if not for the violence, but that's not the same as preventing him from wishing something he is wishing.) The fact that violence can't be done directly to the will doesn't, however, mean that violence can't cause involuntariness, as St. Thomas shows in article 5. The acts of the will are all voluntary, so whatever acts against the will is called involuntary. (Similarly, whatever acts against the natural appetite is called unnatural.) If I am forced by violence to sit where I do not wish to sit, then my sitting is involuntary (and therefore not an act that is either good or evil). Labels: Treatise on Human Acts Link | 0 comments | Tweet
The voluntary and the involuntary, pt. 1
As St. Thomas puts it, "those acts are properly called human which are voluntary, because the will is the rational appetite, which is proper to man." In ST I-II, 6, he discusses what makes an act voluntary, and what might make what would otherwise be a voluntary act involuntary. In Article 1, he distinguishes voluntary acts and natural acts (his example of a natural act is a stone falling). Both are acting upon a principle that is intrinsic or internal to the actor, but in a voluntary act there is knowledge of the end or purpose of the act. In Article 2, he argues that irrational animals can act voluntarily, with "imperfect knowledge" exercised "through their senses and their natural estimative power." In Article 3, he identifies two ways in which you can speak of something as "voluntary" even when there is no corresponding act: you can perform the internal act of willing not to act (e.g., "I think I won't help him up"); or you can fail to perform even the internal act of willing in a situation when you can and ought to act. Thus, though St. Thomas doesn't mention it here, we can speak of "sins of omission," even understanding that each sin is a chosen act. Labels: Treatise on Human Acts Link | 0 comments | Tweet Monday, February 08, 2010
A basic review
Professional torture apologist1 Marc Thiessen likes to quote a salacious passage2 from Henry Charles Lea's A History of the Inquisition of Spain as a way of demonstrating that "even a remote comparison" between what the Bush Administration (in which Thiessen worked as a speechwriter) did to its prisoners and what the Spanish Inquisition did to its prisoners is a "canard," a "ridiculous argument" that "even a basic review of the facts makes clear" can only be made by someone "completely uninformed." Here's the full passage:
The right-hand column contains the bits that, I assume, Thiessen thinks justifies his claim: Needless to say, none of this even remotely resembles what was done by the CIA.The left-hand column contains the bits that resemble what was done by the CIA. If that's too many words, let me edit it down to this: The patient strangled and gasped and suffocated....What explains his need to make, repeatedly, the laughable claim that pouring water into the nose and throat of a man strapped upside down to a table doesn't even remotely resemble pouring water into the nose and throat of a man strapped upside down to a trestle? I've already mentioned Thiessen's consequentialism, though I should add that, as far as I can tell, he is at least a sincere consequentialist. That is, he seems to honestly believe that, if waterboarding saves lives, then it can't be wrong. (I contrast this with a cynical consequentialism, according to which, if waterboarding saves lives, then who cares whether it's wrong.) And so we find him making statements like this: I feel obligated to respond, to defend the honor of the courageous men and women of the CIA who kept us safe and who cannot defend themselves.For a consequentialist, honorable end implies honorable means -- and honorable human beings. Having started down this path, though, the cordeles can only tighten. If the CIA agents Thiessen has spoken to had good intentions -- and I have no reason to doubt their good intentions -- then they are honorable people, and if honorable people do honorable things, then what they did can't be dishonorable, so what they did can't be torture. And if what they did can't be torture, then what makes "water-torture" torture can't be the water, can't be the strangling and gasping and suffocating, so it must be the cruelty with which the victim is held in place. And if a moment's thought shows how ridiculous that is, then a moment's thought shows that these honorable people did something dishonorable. But that's impossible, so a moment's thought is impossible, so a moment's thought must be avoided by declaring the thought a canard, ridiculous, completely uninformed, near-perfect ignorance. The result is a best-selling apologist for torture whose argument reduces to, "Is not, is not, is not!" 1. Marc Thiessen would deny being a torture apologist, because he denies waterboarding is torture. I see no reason to follow him in his confusion. That he is a professional apologist he can't deny, since he's written an apologetical book on the subject. 2. It's a small point, but let me make it: Henry Charles Lea, though a respected historian of his day, wrote with a marked anti-Catholic bias. Thiessen, then, would have us compare a description of one activity written by someone biased against the organization sponsoring it with a description of a similar activity written by someone biased in favor of the organization sponsoring it. This is not to say either description is inaccurate, merely that the author's bias will naturally affect the description given, and that comparison between two descriptions ought to account for these differences. Labels: On torture Link | 72 comments | Tweet
Boy, I don't know about this one
On the one hand, Dominicans. ![]() On the other hand, Oprah. I'm just not... I can't really.... Oh, well. I report, you decide. Link | 1 comments | Tweet Sunday, February 07, 2010
Brother Know-it-all's Rules for Good Blogging
#17: If you have drafted a post that will leave readers unsure whether you're that dumb or that dishonest, then you should delete the post and link to a video of cute kittens. Link | 8 comments | Tweet Saturday, February 06, 2010
I'd appreciate it
The only people cooler than lay brothers are cloistered nuns. Link | 0 comments | Tweet Tuesday, February 02, 2010
Where does God's presence need to be made known?
There are a couple of prayers in Morning Prayer for the Feast of the Presentation that suggested something new to me: You are the consolation of Israel, recognised by the righteous man Simeon when he saw you in the temple:I sometimes wonder about Anna. We get more of a biography of her than of many people mentioned in the Gospels, yet not one word of her prophecy or preaching. Maybe -- and don't bother checking Luke for scriptural support, because I'm just making this up -- one reason Simeon and Anna are both mentioned is to signify the dual role of prophecy: to speak to the Church and to speak to the nations. Simeon blessed and encouraged the Holy Family. Anna spoke to all who were awaiting the redemption of Israel. The Church needs both kinds of prophets -- or maybe I should say both kinds of prophecies, since each of us is able, in some way, to do both. Link | 10 comments | Tweet Monday, February 01, 2010
There's no such thing as unchosen sin
Calumny, as you know, is the act of making a remark contrary to the truth that harms the reputation of another. Suppose a friend asks you for your opinion about a local tradesman. You reply, "That guy? He does shoddy work at a higher price than his competitors." This is fine, if you happen to know that he does shoddy work at a higher price than his competitors. But if he doesn't, you've committed the sin of calumny. Now, what if your friend mispronounced the name of the tradesman, one who happens to be competent and inexpensive, or if your memory of the tradesman's quality and price is faulty through no fault of your own? Suppose you make an honest mistake, and unwittingly tell your friend something that is contrary to the truth that harms the tradesman's reputation. Assuming you aren't culpable for the mistake, then you have not committed calumny. But... we still have a remark contrary to the truth being spoken. We still have harm to a reputation. Where'd the calumny go? Calumny is a sin, which means it's an act chosen by a moral actor. But if you've made an honest mistake, then you have not chosen to make a remark contrary to the truth. If you don't make a choice, you don't commit a sin. It's not that, objectively speaking, calumny happened but you aren't culpable. Calumny didn't happen. Link | 18 comments | Tweet
Moral math!
For a just man shall fall seven times...If he's a just man, though, he must have the habit of justice, which means he habitually doesn't fall. I don't know of a hard and fast rule for determining whether someone does something habitually, so let me propose for the sake of argument that you need to do something right at least twice as often as you do it wrong for you to be said to have the habit of doing it right. If the just man falls seven times, then, he doesn't fall at least fourteen times. Traditionally, the proverb has been interpreted as meaning that the just man falls seven times a day. Thus we have (rounding down) a minimum of twenty opportunities a day for the just man to fall. Is there any reason to suppose that the just man has more opportunities than anyone else? We might suppose his reputation has put him in a position to make more choices than the average person, but in general I think we can get away with 20 as a threshold number of moral choices people make every day. In any event, we surely all make more than 20 choices a day, and we might notionally rank them in decreasing order of how much intellect and will are brought to bear on them. The choice of answering an email might rank higher than the choice of passing a slow car, which might rank higher than the choice of putting a dirty spoon in the sink. Of your notional Top 20 Moral Choices on a typical day, how many of them would you say are real puzzlers? We Internet natterers spend a great deal of time nattering about identical twins and violent lunatics and amnesia and amputating arms and all the cool scenarios that test the boundaries of how moral principles are formulated and how moral action is analyzed. But [almost] nobody spends much time at all actually living and acting in these scenarios. Ordinarily, our choices are ordinary. Ordinarily, the moral issue isn't whether I knew or ought to have known that the gun was loaded. Ordinarily, the moral issue is whether what I choose to do is something I, and everyone else, know or ought to know is right. Link | 30 comments | Tweet
|